Assignment: Theodore Dalrymple
Assignment: Theodore Dalrymple
Permalink:
Assignment: Theodore Dalrymple The Roads to Serfdom People in Britain who lived through World War II do not remember it with anything like the horror one might have expected. In fact, they often remember it as the best time of their lives. Spring 2005 People in Britain who lived through World War II do not remember it with anything like the horror one might have expected. In fact, they often remember it as the best time of their lives. Even allowing for the tendency of time to burnish unpleasant memories with a patina of romance, this is extraordinary. The war, after all, was a time of material shortage, terror, and loss: what could possibly have been good about it? The answer, of course, is that it provided a powerful existential meaning and purpose. The population suffered at the hands of an easily identifiable external enemy, whose evil intentions it became the overriding purpose of the whole nation to thwart. A unified and preeminent national goal provided respite from the peacetime cacophony of complaint, bickering, and social division. And privation for a purpose brings its own content. The war having instantaneously created a nostalgia for the sense of unity and transcendent purpose that prevailed in those years, the population naturally enough asked why such a mood could not persist into the peace that followed. Why couldn‟t the dedication of millions, centrally coordinated by the government—a coordinated dedication that had produced unprecedented quantities of aircraft and munitions—be adapted to defeat what London School of Economics head Sir William Beveridge, in his wartime report on social services that was to usher in the full-scale welfare state in Britain, called the “five giants on the road to reconstruction”: Want, Disease, Ignorance, Squalor, and Idleness? http://www.city-journal.org/index.html By the time Beveridge published his report in 1942, most of the intellectuals of the day assumed that the government, and only the government, could accomplish these desirable goals. Indeed, it all seemed so simple a matter that only the cupidity and stupidity of the rich could have prevented these ends from already having been achieved. The Beveridge Report states, for example, that want “could have been abolished in Britain before the present war” and that “the income available to the British people was ample for such a purpose.” It was just a matter of dividing the national income cake into more equal slices by means of redistributive taxation. If the political will was there, the way was there; there was no need to worry about effects on wealth creation or any other adverse effects. For George Orwell, writing a year before the Beveridge Report, matters were equally straightforward. “Socialism,” he wrote, “is usually defined as „common ownership of the means of production.‟ Crudely: the State, representing the whole nation, owns everything, and everyone is a state employee. . . . Socialism . . . can solve the problems of production and consumption. . . . The State simply calculates what goods will be needed and does its best to produce them. Production is only limited by the amount of labour and raw materials.” A few, equally simple measures would help bring about a better, more just and equitable society. Orwell recommended “i) Nationalization of land, mines, railways, banks and major industries”; “ii) Limitation of incomes, on such a scale that the highest does not exceed the lowest by more than ten to one”; and “iii) Reform of the educational system along democratic lines.” By this last, he meant the total prohibition of private education. He assumed that the culture, which he esteemed but which nevertheless was a product of the very system he so disliked, would take care of itself. It would hardly be an exaggeration to say that, by the time Orwell wrote, his collectivist philosophy was an intellectual orthodoxy from which hardly anyone in Britain would dare dissent, at least very strongly. “We are all socialists now,” declared Bernard Shaw 40 years before Orwell put forward his modest proposals. And before him, Oscar Wilde, in “The Soul of Man under Socialism,” accepted as incontrovertible—as not even worth supporting with evidence or argument, so obviously true was it—that poverty was the inescapable consequence of private property, and that one man‟s wealth was another man‟s destitution. And before Wilde, John Ruskin had argued, in Unto This Last, that a market in labor was both unnecessary and productive of misery. After all, he said, many wages were set according to an abstract (which is to say a moral) conception of the value of the job; so why should not all wages be set in the same way? Would this not avoid the unjust, irrational, and frequently harsh variations to which a labor market exposed people? Ruskin was right that there are indeed jobs whose wages are fixed by an approximate notion of moral appropriateness. The salary of the president of the United States is not set according to the vagaries of the labor market; nor would the number of candidates for the post change much if it were halved or doubled. But if every wage in the United States were fixed in the same way, wages would soon cease to mean very much. The economy would be demonetized, the impersonal medium of money being replaced in the allocation of goods and services by personal influence and political connection—precisely what happened in the Soviet Union. Every economic transaction would become an expression of political power. The growing spirit of collectivism in Britain during the war provoked an Austrian economist who had taken refuge there, F. A. von Hayek, to write a polemical counterblast to the trend: The Road to Serfdom, published in 1944. It went through six printings in its first year, but its effect on majority opinion was, for many years to come, negligible. Hayek believed that while intellectuals in modern liberal democracies—those to whom he somewhat contemptuously referred as the professional secondhand dealers in ideas—did not usually have direct access to power, the theories that they diffused among the population ultimately had a profound, even determining, influence upon their society. Intellectuals are of far greater importance than appears at first sight. Hayek was therefore alarmed at the general acceptance of collectivist arguments—or worse still, assumptions—by British intellectuals of all classes. He had seen the process— or thought he had seen it—before, in the German-speaking world from which he came, and he feared that Britain would likewise slide down the totalitarian path. Moreover, at the time he wrote, the “success” of the two major totalitarian powers in Europe, Nazi Germany and Soviet Russia, seemed to have justified the belief that a plan was necessary to coordinate human activity toward a consciously chosen goal. For George Orwell, the difference between the two tyrannies was one of ends, not of means: he held up Nazi Germany as an exemplar of economic efficiency resulting from central planning, but he deplored the ends that efficiency accomplished. While the idea behind Nazism was “human inequality, the superiority of Germans to all other races, the right of Germany to rule the world,” socialism (of which, of course, the Soviet Union was the only exemplar at the time) “aims, ultimately, at a world-state of free and equal human beings.” Same means, different ends: but Orwell, at this point in his intellectual development, saw nothing intrinsically objectionable in the means themselves, or that they must inevitably lead to tyranny and oppression, independently of the ends for which they were deployed. Against the collectivists, Hayek brought powerful—and to my mind obvious—arguments, that, however, were scarcely new or original. Nevertheless, it is often, perhaps usually, more important to remind people of old truths than to introduce them to new ones. Hayek pointed out that the wartime unity of purpose was atypical; in more normal times, people had a far greater, indeed an infinite, variety of ends, and anyone with the power to adjudicate among them in the name of a conscious overall national plan, allowing a few but forbidding most, would exert vastly more power than the most bloated plutocrat of socialist propaganda had ever done in a free-market society. Orwell‟s assertion that the state would simply calculate what was needed airily overlooked the difficulties of the matter, as well as his proposal‟s implications for freedom. The “directing brains,” as Orwell called them, would have to decide how many hairpins, how many shoelaces, were “needed” by the population under their purview. They would have to make untold millions of such decisions, likewise coordinating the production of all components of each product, on the basis of their own arbitrary notions of what their fellow citizens needed. Orwell‟s goal, therefore, was a society in which the authorities strictly rationed everything; for him, and untold intellectuals like him, only rationing was rational. It takes little effort of the imagination to see what this control would mean for the exercise of liberty. Among other things, people would have to be assigned work regardless of their own preferences. Collectivist thinking arose, according to Hayek, from impatience, a lack of historical perspective, and an arrogant belief that, because we have made so much technological progress, everything must be susceptible to human control. While we take material advance for granted as soon as it occurs, we consider remaining social problems as unprecedented and anomalous, and we propose solutions that actually make more difficult further progress of the very kind that we have forgotten ever happened. While everyone saw the misery the Great Depression caused, for example, few realized that, even so, living standards actually continued to rise for the majority. If we live entirely in the moment, as if the world were created exactly as we now find it, we are almost bound to propose solutions that bring even worse problems in their wake. In reaction to the unemployment rampant in what W. H. Auden called “the low dishonest decade” before the war, the Beveridge Report suggested that it was government‟s function to maximize security of income and employment. This proposition was bound to appeal strongly to people who remembered mass unemployment and collapsing wages; but however high-minded and generous it might have sounded, it was wrong. Hayek pointed out that you can‟t give everyone a job irrespective of demand without sparking severe inflation. And you can no more protect one group of workers‟ wages against market fluctuations without penalizing another group than you can discriminate positively in one group‟s favor without discriminating negatively against another. This is so, and it is beyond any individual human‟s control that it should be so. Therefore, no amount of planning would ever make Beveridge‟s goals possible, however desirable they might be in the abstract. But just because a goal is logically impossible to achieve does not mean that it must be without effect on human affairs. As the history of the twentieth century demonstrates perhaps better than any other, impossible goals have had at least as great an effect on human existence as more limited and possible ones.
Assignment: Theodore Dalrymple The Roads to Serfdom People in Britain who lived through World War II do not remember it with anything like the horror one might have expected. In fact, they often remember it as the best time of their lives. Spring 2005 People in Britain who lived through World War II do not remember it with anything like the horror one might have expected. In fact, they often remember it as the best time of their lives. Even allowing for the tendency of time to burnish unpleasant memories with a patina of romance, this is extraordinary. The war, after all, was a time of material shortage, terror, and loss: what could possibly have been good about it? The answer, of course, is that it provided a powerful existential meaning and purpose. The population suffered at the hands of an easily identifiable external enemy, whose evil intentions it became the overriding purpose of the whole nation to thwart. A unified and preeminent national goal provided respite from the peacetime cacophony of complaint, bickering, and social division. And privation for a purpose brings its own content. The war having instantaneously created a nostalgia for the sense of unity and transcendent purpose that prevailed in those years, the population naturally enough asked why such a mood could not persist into the peace that followed. Why couldn‟t the dedication of millions, centrally coordinated by the government—a coordinated dedication that had produced unprecedented quantities of aircraft and munitions—be adapted to defeat what London School of Economics head Sir William Beveridge, in his wartime report on social services that was to usher in the full-scale welfare state in Britain, called the “five giants on the road to reconstruction”: Want, Disease, Ignorance, Squalor, and Idleness? http://www.city-journal.org/index.html By the time Beveridge published his report in 1942, most of the intellectuals of the day assumed that the government, and only the government, could accomplish these desirable goals. Indeed, it all seemed so simple a matter that only the cupidity and stupidity of the rich could have prevented these ends from already having been achieved. The Beveridge Report states, for example, that want “could have been abolished in Britain before the present war” and that “the income available to the British people was ample for such a purpose.” It was just a matter of dividing the national income cake into more equal slices by means of redistributive taxation. If the political will was there, the way was there; there was no need to worry about effects on wealth creation or any other adverse effects. For George Orwell, writing a year before the Beveridge Report, matters were equally straightforward. “Socialism,” he wrote, “is usually defined as „common ownership of the means of production.‟ Crudely: the State, representing the whole nation, owns everything, and everyone is a state employee. . . . Socialism . . . can solve the problems of production and consumption. . . . The State simply calculates what goods will be needed and does its best to produce them. Production is only limited by the amount of labour and raw materials.” A few, equally simple measures would help bring about a better, more just and equitable society. Orwell recommended “i) Nationalization of land, mines, railways, banks and major industries”; “ii) Limitation of incomes, on such a scale that the highest does not exceed the lowest by more than ten to one”; and “iii) Reform of the educational system along democratic lines.” By this last, he meant the total prohibition of private education. He assumed that the culture, which he esteemed but which nevertheless was a product of the very system he so disliked, would take care of itself. It would hardly be an exaggeration to say that, by the time Orwell wrote, his collectivist philosophy was an intellectual orthodoxy from which hardly anyone in Britain would dare dissent, at least very strongly. “We are all socialists now,” declared Bernard Shaw 40 years before Orwell put forward his modest proposals. And before him, Oscar Wilde, in “The Soul of Man under Socialism,” accepted as incontrovertible—as not even worth supporting with evidence or argument, so obviously true was it—that poverty was the inescapable consequence of private property, and that one man‟s wealth was another man‟s destitution. And before Wilde, John Ruskin had argued, in Unto This Last, that a market in labor was both unnecessary and productive of misery. After all, he said, many wages were set according to an abstract (which is to say a moral) conception of the value of the job; so why should not all wages be set in the same way? Would this not avoid the unjust, irrational, and frequently harsh variations to which a labor market exposed people? Ruskin was right that there are indeed jobs whose wages are fixed by an approximate notion of moral appropriateness. The salary of the president of the United States is not set according to the vagaries of the labor market; nor would the number of candidates for the post change much if it were halved or doubled. But if every wage in the United States were fixed in the same way, wages would soon cease to mean very much. The economy would be demonetized, the impersonal medium of money being replaced in the allocation of goods and services by personal influence and political connection—precisely what happened in the Soviet Union. Every economic transaction would become an expression of political power. The growing spirit of collectivism in Britain during the war provoked an Austrian economist who had taken refuge there, F. A. von Hayek, to write a polemical counterblast to the trend: The Road to Serfdom, published in 1944. It went through six printings in its first year, but its effect on majority opinion was, for many years to come, negligible. Hayek believed that while intellectuals in modern liberal democracies—those to whom he somewhat contemptuously referred as the professional secondhand dealers in ideas—did not usually have direct access to power, the theories that they diffused among the population ultimately had a profound, even determining, influence upon their society. Intellectuals are of far greater importance than appears at first sight. Hayek was therefore alarmed at the general acceptance of collectivist arguments—or worse still, assumptions—by British intellectuals of all classes. He had seen the process— or thought he had seen it—before, in the German-speaking world from which he came, and he feared that Britain would likewise slide down the totalitarian path. Moreover, at the time he wrote, the “success” of the two major totalitarian powers in Europe, Nazi Germany and Soviet Russia, seemed to have justified the belief that a plan was necessary to coordinate human activity toward a consciously chosen goal. For George Orwell, the difference between the two tyrannies was one of ends, not of means: he held up Nazi Germany as an exemplar of economic efficiency resulting from central planning, but he deplored the ends that efficiency accomplished. While the idea behind Nazism was “human inequality, the superiority of Germans to all other races, the right of Germany to rule the world,” socialism (of which, of course, the Soviet Union was the only exemplar at the time) “aims, ultimately, at a world-state of free and equal human beings.” Same means, different ends: but Orwell, at this point in his intellectual development, saw nothing intrinsically objectionable in the means themselves, or that they must inevitably lead to tyranny and oppression, independently of the ends for which they were deployed. Against the collectivists, Hayek brought powerful—and to my mind obvious—arguments, that, however, were scarcely new or original. Nevertheless, it is often, perhaps usually, more important to remind people of old truths than to introduce them to new ones. Hayek pointed out that the wartime unity of purpose was atypical; in more normal times, people had a far greater, indeed an infinite, variety of ends, and anyone with the power to adjudicate among them in the name of a conscious overall national plan, allowing a few but forbidding most, would exert vastly more power than the most bloated plutocrat of socialist propaganda had ever done in a free-market society. Orwell‟s assertion that the state would simply calculate what was needed airily overlooked the difficulties of the matter, as well as his proposal‟s implications for freedom. The “directing brains,” as Orwell called them, would have to decide how many hairpins, how many shoelaces, were “needed” by the population under their purview. They would have to make untold millions of such decisions, likewise coordinating the production of all components of each product, on the basis of their own arbitrary notions of what their fellow citizens needed. Orwell‟s goal, therefore, was a society in which the authorities strictly rationed everything; for him, and untold intellectuals like him, only rationing was rational. It takes little effort of the imagination to see what this control would mean for the exercise of liberty. Among other things, people would have to be assigned work regardless of their own preferences. Collectivist thinking arose, according to Hayek, from impatience, a lack of historical perspective, and an arrogant belief that, because we have made so much technological progress, everything must be susceptible to human control. While we take material advance for granted as soon as it occurs, we consider remaining social problems as unprecedented and anomalous, and we propose solutions that actually make more difficult further progress of the very kind that we have forgotten ever happened. While everyone saw the misery the Great Depression caused, for example, few realized that, even so, living standards actually continued to rise for the majority. If we live entirely in the moment, as if the world were created exactly as we now find it, we are almost bound to propose solutions that bring even worse problems in their wake. In reaction to the unemployment rampant in what W. H. Auden called “the low dishonest decade” before the war, the Beveridge Report suggested that it was government‟s function to maximize security of income and employment. This proposition was bound to appeal strongly to people who remembered mass unemployment and collapsing wages; but however high-minded and generous it might have sounded, it was wrong. Hayek pointed out that you can‟t give everyone a job irrespective of demand without sparking severe inflation. And you can no more protect one group of workers‟ wages against market fluctuations without penalizing another group than you can discriminate positively in one group‟s favor without discriminating negatively against another. This is so, and it is beyond any individual human‟s control that it should be so. Therefore, no amount of planning would ever make Beveridge‟s goals possible, however desirable they might be in the abstract. But just because a goal is logically impossible to achieve does not mean that it must be without effect on human affairs. As the history of the twentieth century demonstrates perhaps better than any other, impossible goals have had at least as great an effect on human existence as more limited and possible ones.
Theodore Dalrymple
The Roads to Serfdom
People in Britain who lived through World War II do not remember it with anything
like the horror one might have expected. In fact, they often remember it as the best time
of their lives.
Spring 2005
People in Britain who lived through World War II do not remember it with anything like the horror one might have expected. In fact, they often remember it as the best time
of their lives. Even allowing for the tendency of time to burnish unpleasant memories
with a patina of romance, this is extraordinary. The war, after all, was a time of material
shortage, terror, and loss: what could possibly have been good about it?
The answer, of course, is that it provided a powerful existential meaning and purpose.
The population suffered at the hands of an easily identifiable external enemy, whose evil
intentions it became the overriding purpose of the whole nation to thwart. A unified and
preeminent national goal provided respite from the peacetime cacophony of complaint,
bickering, and social division. And privation for a purpose brings its own content.
The war having instantaneously created a nostalgia for the sense of unity and
transcendent purpose that prevailed in those years, the population naturally enough
asked why such a mood could not persist into the peace that followed. Why couldn‟t the
dedication of millions, centrally coordinated by the government—a coordinated
dedication that had produced unprecedented quantities of aircraft and munitions—be
adapted to defeat what London School of Economics head Sir William Beveridge, in his
wartime report on social services that was to usher in the full-scale welfare state in
Britain, called the “five giants on the road to reconstruction”: Want, Disease, Ignorance,
Squalor, and Idleness?
By the time Beveridge published his report in 1942, most of the intellectuals of the day assumed that the government, and only the government, could accomplish these
desirable goals. Indeed, it all seemed so simple a matter that only the cupidity and
stupidity of the rich could have prevented these ends from already having been achieved.
The Beveridge Report states, for example, that want “could have been abolished in
Britain before the present war” and that “the income available to the British people was
ample for such a purpose.” It was just a matter of dividing the national income cake into
more equal slices by means of redistributive taxation. If the political will was there, the
way was there; there was no need to worry about effects on wealth creation or any other
adverse effects.
For George Orwell, writing a year before the Beveridge Report, matters were equally
straightforward. “Socialism,” he wrote, “is usually defined as „common ownership of the
means of production.‟ Crudely: the State, representing the whole nation, owns
everything, and everyone is a state employee. . . . Socialism . . . can solve the problems of
production and consumption. . . . The State simply calculates what goods will be needed
and does its best to produce them. Production is only limited by the amount of labour
and raw materials.”
A few, equally simple measures would help bring about a better, more just and equitable
society. Orwell recommended “i) Nationalization of land, mines, railways, banks and
major industries”; “ii)
Theodore Dalrymple
The Roads to Serfdom
People in Britain who lived through World War II do not remember it with anything
like the horror one might have expected. In fact, they often remember it as the best time
of their lives.
Spring 2005
People in Britain who lived through World War II do not remember it with anything like the horror one might have expected. In fact, they often remember it as the best time
of their lives. Even allowing for the tendency of time to burnish unpleasant memories
with a patina of romance, this is extraordinary. The war, after all, was a time of material
shortage, terror, and loss: what could possibly have been good about it?
The answer, of course, is that it provided a powerful existential meaning and purpose.
The population suffered at the hands of an easily identifiable external enemy, whose evil
intentions it became the overriding purpose of the whole nation to thwart. A unified and
preeminent national goal provided respite from the peacetime cacophony of complaint,
bickering, and social division. And privation for a purpose brings its own content.
The war having instantaneously created a nostalgia for the sense of unity and
transcendent purpose that prevailed in those years, the population naturally enough
asked why such a mood could not persist into the peace that followed. Why couldn‟t the
dedication of millions, centrally coordinated by the government—a coordinated
dedication that had produced unprecedented quantities of aircraft and munitions—be
adapted to defeat what London School of Economics head Sir William Beveridge, in his
wartime report on social services that was to usher in the full-scale welfare state in
Britain, called the “five giants on the road to reconstruction”: Want, Disease, Ignorance,
Squalor, and Idleness?
By the time Beveridge published his report in 1942, most of the intellectuals of the day assumed that the government, and only the government, could accomplish these
desirable goals. Indeed, it all seemed so simple a matter that only the cupidity and
stupidity of the rich could have prevented these ends from already having been achieved.
The Beveridge Report states, for example, that want “could have been abolished in
Britain before the present war” and that “the income available to the British people was
ample for such a purpose.” It was just a matter of dividing the national income cake into
more equal slices by means of redistributive taxation. If the political will was there, the
way was there; there was no need to worry about effects on wealth creation or any other
adverse effects.
For George Orwell, writing a year before the Beveridge Report, matters were equally
straightforward. “Socialism,” he wrote, “is usually defined as „common ownership of the
means of production.‟ Crudely: the State, representing the whole nation, owns
everything, and everyone is a state employee. . . . Socialism . . . can solve the problems of
production and consumption. . . . The State simply calculates what goods will be needed
and does its best to produce them. Production is only limited by the amount of labour
and raw materials.”
A few, equally simple measures would help bring about a better, more just and equitable
society. Orwell recommended “i) Nationalization of land, mines, railways, banks and
major industries”; “ii) Limitation of incomes, on such a scale that the highest does not
exceed the lowest by more than ten to one”; and “iii) Reform of the educational system
along democratic lines.” By this last, he meant the total prohibition of private education.
He assumed that the culture, which he esteemed but which nevertheless was a product of
the very system he so disliked, would take care of itself.
It would hardly be an exaggeration to say that, by the time Orwell wrote, his collectivist
philosophy was an intellectual orthodoxy from which hardly anyone in Britain would
dare dissent, at least very strongly. “We are all socialists now,” declared Bernard Shaw
40 years before Orwell put forward his modest proposals. And before him, Oscar Wilde,
in “The Soul of Man under Socialism,” accepted as incontrovertible—as not even worth
supporting with evidence or argument, so obviously true was it—that poverty was the
inescapable consequence of private property, and that one man‟s wealth was another
man‟s destitution. And before Wilde, John Ruskin had argued, in Unto This Last, that a
market in labor was both unnecessary and productive of misery. After all, he said, many
wages were set according to an abstract (which is to say a moral) conception of the value
of the job; so why should not all wages be set in the same way? Would this not avoid the
unjust, irrational, and frequently harsh variations to which a labor market exposed
people?
Ruskin was right that there are indeed jobs whose wages are fixed by an approximate
notion of moral appropriateness. The salary of the president of the United States is not
set according to the vagaries of the labor market; nor would the number of candidates for
the post change much if it were halved or doubled. But if every wage in the United States
were fixed in the same way, wages would soon cease to mean very much. The economy
would be demonetized, the impersonal medium of money being replaced in the
allocation of goods and services by personal influence and political connection—precisely
what happened in the Soviet Union. Every economic transaction would become an
expression of political power.
They would have to make untold millions of such decisions, likewise coordinating the
production of all components of each product, on the basis of their own arbitrary notions
of what their fellow citizens needed. Orwell‟s goal, therefore, was a society in which the
authorities strictly rationed everything; for him, and untold intellectuals like him, only
rationing was rational. It takes little effort of the imagination to see what this control
would mean for the exercise of liberty. Among other things, people would have to be
assigned work regardless of their own preferences.
Collectivist thinking arose, according to Hayek, from impatience, a lack of historical
perspective, and an arrogant belief that, because we have made so much technological
progress, everything must be susceptible to human control. While we take material
advance for granted as soon as it occurs, we consider remaining social problems as
unprecedented and anomalous, and we propose solutions that actually make more
difficult further progress of the very kind that we have forgotten ever happened. While
everyone saw the misery the Great Depression caused, for example, few realized that,
even so, living standards actually continued to rise for the majority. If we live entirely in
the moment, as if the world were created exactly as we now find it, we are almost bound
to propose solutions that bring even worse problems in their wake.
In reaction to the unemployment rampant in what W. H. Auden called “the low
dishonest decade” before the war, the Beveridge Report suggested that it was
government‟s function to maximize security of income and employment. This
proposition was bound to appeal strongly to people who remembered mass
unemployment and collapsing wages; but however high-minded and generous it might
have sounded, it was wrong. Hayek pointed out that you can‟t give everyone a job
irrespective of demand without sparking severe inflation. And you can no more protect
one group of workers‟ wages against market fluctuations without penalizing another
group than you can discriminate positively in one group‟s favor without discriminating
negatively against another. This is so, and it is beyond any individual human‟s control
that it should be so. Therefore, no amount of planning would ever make Beveridge‟s
goals possible, however desirable they might be in the abstract.
But just because a goal is logically impossible to achieve does not mean that it must be
without effect on human affairs. As the history of the twentieth century demonstrates
perhaps better than any other, impossible goals have had at least as great an effect on
human existence as more limited and possible ones.
”; and “iii) Reform of the educational system
along democratic lines.” By this last, he meant the total prohibition of private education.
He assumed that the culture, which he esteemed but which nevertheless was a product of
the very system he so disliked, would take care of itself.
It would hardly be an exaggeration to say that, by the time Orwell wrote, his collectivist
philosophy was an intellectual orthodoxy from which hardly anyone in Britain would
dare dissent, at least very strongly. “We are all socialists now,” declared Bernard Shaw
40 years before Orwell put forward his modest proposals. And before him, Oscar Wilde,
in “The Soul of Man under Socialism,” accepted as incontrovertible—as not even worth
supporting with evidence or argument, so obviously true was it—that poverty was the
inescapable consequence of private property, and that one man‟s wealth was another
man‟s destitution. And before Wilde, John Ruskin had argued, in Unto This Last, that a
market in labor was both unnecessary and productive of misery. After all, he said, many
wages were set according to an abstract (which is to say a moral) conception of the value
of the job; so why should not all wages be set in the same way? Would this not avoid the
unjust, irrational, and frequently harsh variations to which a labor market exposed
people?
Ruskin was right that there are indeed jobs whose wages are fixed by an approximate
notion of moral appropriateness. The salary of the president of the United States is not
set according to the vagaries of the labor market; nor would the number of candidates for
the post change much if it were halved or doubled. But if every wage in the United States
were fixed in the same way, wages would soon cease to mean very much. The economy
would be demonetized, the impersonal medium of money being replaced in the
allocation of goods and services by personal influence and political connection—precisely
what happened in the Soviet Union. Every economic transaction would become an
expression of political power.
The growing spirit of collectivism in Britain during the war provoked an Austrian economist who had taken refuge there, F. A. von Hayek, to write a polemical
counterblast to the trend: The Road to Serfdom, published in 1944. It went through six
printings in its first year, but its effect on majority opinion was, for many years to come,
negligible. Hayek believed that while intellectuals in modern liberal democracies—those
to whom he somewhat contemptuously referred as the professional secondhand dealers
in ideas—did not usually have direct access to power, the theories that they diffused
among the population ultimately had a profound, even determining, influence upon their
society. Intellectuals are of far greater importance than appears at first sight.
Hayek was therefore alarmed at the general acceptance of collectivist arguments—or
worse still, assumptions—by British intellectuals of all classes. He had seen the process—
or thought he had seen it—before, in the German-speaking world from which he came,
and he feared that Britain would likewise slide down the totalitarian path. Moreover, at
the time he wrote, the “success” of the two major totalitarian powers in Europe, Nazi
Germany and Soviet Russia, seemed to have justified the belief that a plan was necessary
to coordinate human activity toward a consciously chosen goal. For George Orwell, the
difference between the two tyrannies was one of ends, not of means: he held up Nazi
Germany as an exemplar of economic efficiency resulting from central planning, but he
deplored the ends that efficiency accomplished. While the idea behind Nazism was
“human inequality, the superiority of Germans to all other races, the right of Germany to
rule the world,” socialism (of which, of course, the Soviet Union was the only exemplar at
the time) “aims, ultimately, at a world-state of free and equal human beings.” Same
means, different ends: but Orwell, at this point in his intellectual development, saw
nothing intrinsically objectionable in the means themselves, or that they must inevitably
lead to tyranny and oppression, independently of the ends for which they were deployed.
Against the collectivists, Hayek brought powerful—and to my mind obvious—arguments,
that, however, were scarcely new or original. Nevertheless, it is often, perhaps usually,
more important to remind people of old truths than to introduce them to new ones.
that it should be so. Therefore, no amount of planning would ever make Beveridge‟s
goals possible, however desirable they might be in the abstract.
But just because a goal is logically impossible to achieve does not mean that it must be
without effect on human affairs. As the history of the twentieth century demonstrates
perhaps better than any other, impossible goals have had at least as great an effect on
human existence as more limited and possible ones.